-
198Kantian moral motivation and the feeling of respectJournal of the History of Philosophy 31 (3): 421-435. 1993.
-
195Maxims in Kant's practical philosophyJournal of the History of Philosophy 44 (1): 65-83. 2006.: A standard interpretation of Kantian "maxims" sees them as expressing reasons for action, implying that we cannot act without a maxim. But recent challenges to this interpretation claim that Kant viewed acting on maxims as optional. Kant's understanding of maxims derives from Christian Wolff, who regarded maxims as major premises of the practical syllogism. This supports the standard interpretation. Yet Kant also viewed commitments to maxims as essential for virtue and character development, w…Read more
-
164Late modern philosophy: essential readings with commentary (edited book)Wiley-Blackwell. 2007.Part of the Blackwell Readings in the History of Philosophy series, this survey of late modern philosophy focuses on the key texts and philosophers of the period whose beliefs changed the course of western thought.
-
136False Negatives of the Categorical ImperativeMind 124 (493): 177-200. 2015.The categorical imperative can be construed as a universalization test for moral permissibility. False negatives of the categorical imperative would be maxims failing this test, despite the permissibility of their actions; maxims like: ‘I’ll withdraw all my savings on April 15th’. Examples of purported false negatives familiar from the literature can be grouped into three general categories, and dispatched by applying category-specific methods for proper formulation of their maxims, or for prope…Read more
-
110Kant’s Derivation of the Formula of Universal LawDialogue 49 (1): 113-133. 2010.ABSTRACT: Critics have charged that there are gaps in the logic of Kant’s derivation of the formula of universal law. Here I defend that derivation against these charges, partly by emphasizing a neglected teleological principle that Kant alluded to in his argument, and partly by clarifying what he meant by actions’ “conformity to universal law.” He meant that actions conform to universal law just when their maxims can belong to a unified system of principles. An analogy with objects’ conformity …Read more
-
78Motivation and Moral Choice in Kant’s Theory of Rational AgencyKant Studien 85 (1): 15-31. 1994.
-
76Moral Conflicts in Kantian EthicsHistory of Philosophy Quarterly 8 (1). 1991.After distinguishing three criteria of adequacy for any acceptable moral theory's treatment of moral conflict, or conflicts of duties, I explain how Kant's ethics can satisfy all three. Although Kant denies the possibility of conflicting duties, he does allow conflicting "grounds of obligation." I develop a new interpretation of such conflicts, rejecting one proposed earlier by Onora O'Neill
-
69Hume’s better argument for motivational skepticismPhilosophical Explorations 21 (1): 76-89. 2018.On a standard interpretation, Hume argued that reason is not practical, because its operations are limited to “demonstration” and “probability.” But recent critics claim that by limiting reason’s operations to only these two, his argument begs the question. Despite this, a better argument for motivational skepticism can be found in Hume’s text, one that emphasizes reason’s inability to generate motive force against contrary desires or passions. Nothing can oppose an impulse but a contrary impuls…Read more
-
67The Right to Lie: Kantian Ethics and the Inquiring MurdererAmerican Philosophical Quarterly 49 (4): 331-344. 2012.Few challenges facing Kantian ethics are more famous and formidable than the so-called "case of the inquiring murderer." It appears in some form today in most introductory ethics texts, but it is not a new objection. Even Kant himself was compelled to respond to it, though by most accounts his response was embarrassingly unpersuasive. A more satisfactory reply can be offered to this old objection, however. It will be shown here that Kantian ethics permits lying to inquirers asking wrong question…Read more
-
65Kant's theory of actionOxford University Press. 2009.The theory of action underlying Immanuel Kant's ethical theory is the subject of this book.
-
59Kant's Incorporation Requirement: Freedom and Character in the Empirical WorldCanadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3): 425-451. 2008.In Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason Kant wrote that ‘freedom of the power of choice has the characteristic, entirely peculiar to it, that it cannot be determined to action through any incentive except insofar as the human being has incorporated it into his maxim.’ This is an obscure statement, in both meaning and provenance. Yet almost all recent interpreters of Kant's practical philosophy find it crucial for understanding his theories of freedom and motivation, since it seems to in…Read more
-
26Kant and Political Philosophy (review)Review of Metaphysics 48 (2): 392-393. 1994.Kantian political philosophy is a rich mine, and one which is hardly played out after two centuries. This substantial collection of essays validates both of those claims. Although Kant's moral philosophy has understandably received the lion's share of attention from contemporary philosophers, Beiner and Booth, both political scientists, have gathered essays which nicely illuminate the historical and political facets of Kantian practical philosophy. Anyone interested in Kantian ethics would benef…Read more
-
7Humean CourageIn Ilya Kasavin (ed.), Hume and Contemporary Philosophy, Cambridge Scholars Press. 2012.