Temple University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
Iowa City, Iowa, United States of America
  •  26
    The Epistemology of Spirit Beliefs, written by Hans Van Eyghen
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 14 (1): 79-85. 2023.
  •  114
    Review: Hans Radder: The World Observed/The World Conceived (review)
    Mind 117 (466): 505-507. 2008.
  •  8
    Sensible Animism
    In Tiddy Smith (ed.), Animism and Philosophy of Religion, Springer Verlag. pp. 179-197. 2022.
    Animistic religious thought is extremely widespread, and can be found even in religions practiced by “modern” societies. But it is commonly thought to bear the hallmarks of “primitive” thinking processes, which in the anthropological tradition have typically been taken to involve various cognitive errors. Here I am going to argue that this misunderstands and misrepresents the content of such thinking, which is by no means as unsophisticated as it is usually considered to be. I shall be using Rob…Read more
  •  11
    Theodicy in a Vale of Tears
    In Justin P. McBrayer & Daniel Howard‐Snyder (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Wiley. 2013.
    Theodicies can be distinguished as “hard-nosed” or “good-hearted.” Typical features of each are given. I reject the former; they set the bar too low for God. Considerable discussion is devoted to Eleonore Stump's recent Wandering in Darkness, which sets the standard for good-hearted theodicies. I then develop the notion of a “perfect creature”, a possible being indistinguishable from God except lacking aseity, and argue that God should have created only perfect creatures. Since He did not, He is…Read more
  •  14
    Causation: A Realist Approach
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 605-610. 1990.
  •  10
    Causes and Coincidences (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 465-468. 1995.
  •  130
    Causation and Universals
    Routledge. 1990.
    The world contains objective causal relations and universals, both of which are intimately connected. If these claims are true, they must have far-reaching consequences, breathing new life into the theory of empirical knowledge and reinforcing epistemological realism. Without causes and universals, Professor Fales argues, realism is defeated, and idealism or scepticism wins. Fales begins with a detailed analysis of David Hume's argument that we have no direct experience of necessary connections …Read more
  • Definite Descriptions as Designators
    Mind 85 (n/a): 225. 1976.
  • A Defense of the Given
    Noûs 34 (3): 468-480. 2000.
  •  94
    The attraction between religion and politics is perennial. Sometimes, in its long and checkered history, it has led to an adulterous affair. I want to ask what lies at the heart of this attraction, and whether that can shed any light on the current religious/political scene. But the romance metaphor is at bottom not a good one. I shall argue that, in their originary condition, religion and politics are "closer," both ontologically and in their motivation, than woman and man, closer than siblings…Read more
  • The Structure of Explanations
    Dissertation, Temple University. 1974.
  •  119
    Divine freedom and the choice of a world
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 35 (2). 1994.
  •  120
    Mystical experience as evidence
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 40 (1). 1996.
  •  127
    Divine Intervention
    Faith and Philosophy 14 (2): 170-194. 1997.
    Some philosophers deny that science can investigate the supernatural - specifically, the nature and actions of God. If a divine being is atemporal, then, indeed, this seems plausible - but only, I shall argue, because such a being could not causally interact with anything. Here I discuss in detail two major attempts, those of Stump and Kretzmann, and of Leftow, to make sense of theophysical causation on the supposition that God is eternal. These views are carefully worked out, and their failures…Read more
  •  3
    Causal knowledge: What can psychology teach philosophers
    with Edward A. Wasserman
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 13 (1): 1-28. 1992.
    Theories of how organisms learn about cause-effect relations have a history dating back at least to the associationist/mechanistic hypothesis of David Hume. Some contemporary theories of causal learning are descendants of Hume's mechanistic models of conditioning, but others impute principled, rule-based reasoning. Since even primitive animals are conditionable, it is clear that there are built-in mechanical algorithms that respond to cause/effect relations. The evidence suggests that humans ret…Read more
  •  44
    Scientific explanations of mystical experiences: Evan Fales
    Religious Studies 32 (3): 297-313. 1996.
    In Part I of this paper, I took up a challenge posed by Alston , Wainwright , Yandell , and other theists who hold the rather natural view that mystical experiences provide perceptual contact with God, roughly on a par with the access sense experience affords to the natural world. These theists recognize, at the same time, that the plausibility of this view would be significantly compromised by the possibility of scientifically explaining mystical experiences – especially if a scientific explana…Read more
  •  40
    Are Christians Obliged to Be Pacifists?
    Faith and Philosophy 11 (2): 298-301. 1994.
  •  45
    Relative essentialism
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (4): 349-370. 1979.
  •  2
    Naturalism and physicalism
    In Michael Martin (ed.), , Cambridge University Press. 2007.
  •  40
    Generic universals
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (1). 1982.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  72
    Donnellan on definite descriptions
    Philosophia 6 (2): 289-302. 1976.
    Donnellan's distinction between the referential and attributive uses of definite descriptions is shown not to cover exhaustive and exclusive alternatives but to fix the termini of a continuum of cases. in fact, donnellan's distinction rests on a mixed classification: the referential use, concerned with intended referents regardless of what speakers may say about them; the attributive use, concerned with definite descriptions used in using sentences, that something or other may satisfy. given thi…Read more
  •  80
    Definite descriptions as designators
    Mind 85 (338): 225-238. 1976.
  •  81
    The ontology of social roles
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (2): 139-161. 1977.
  •  10
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 103 (411): 391-395. 1994.
  •  35
    Review of Stewart Goetz, Freedom, Teleology, and Evil (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (8). 2009.
  •  19
    Causation and Induction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1): 113-134. 1984.
  •  184
    Proper Basicality
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2): 373-383. 2004.
    Foundationalist epistemologies, whether internalist or externalist, ground noetic structures in beliefs that are said to be foundational, or properly basic. It is essential to such epistemologies that they provide clear criteria for proper basicality. This proves, 1 argue, to be a thorny task, at least insofar as the goal is to provide a psychologically realistic reconstruction of our actual doxastic practices. I examine some of the difficulties, and suggest some implications, in particular for …Read more