Cornell University
Sage School of Philosophy
PhD, 1960
Ithaca, New York, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
Philosophy of Action
  • Libertarianism
    In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics, Oxford University Press. 2003.
  •  3
    Comments on Plantinga’s two-volume work on warrant
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 403-408. 1995.
  • Norman Malcolm (1911–1990)
    In A. P. Martinich & David Sosa (eds.), A Companion to Analytic Philosophy, Blackwell. 2001.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Knowledge Mind Memory Philosophy of religion.
  •  5
    Philosophy of the Person
    Philosophy of Science 29 (3): 320-322. 1962.
  •  141
    On Mele and Robb’s Indeterministic Frankfurt-Style Case
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (2): 440-446. 2010.
    Alfred Mele and David Robb (1998, 2003) offer what they claim is a counter-example to the principle of alternative possibilities (PAP), the principle that a person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise. In their example, a person makes a decision by his own indeterministic causal process though antecedent circumstances ensure he could not have done otherwise. Specifically, a simultaneously occurring process in him would deterministically cause the decis…Read more
  • Can an Indeterministic Cause Leave a Choice Up to the Agent?
    In David Palmer (ed.), Libertarian Free Will: Contemporary Debates, Oxford University Press. pp. 14-26. 2014.
    This chapter argues for a noncausal libertarian account of free will. According to this account, a person’s free actions cannot be caused at all. The chapter compares its libertarian view to Kane’s event-causal libertarian view. It critiques Kane’s proposals concerning self-forming actions and indeterministic causation. The chapter explains why it thinks that its non-causal view is to be preferred over Kane’s event-causal view. The chapter also discusses the luck objection to libertarianism. The…Read more
  •  4
    Res Cogitans: An Essay in Rational Psychology (review)
    with Sally M. Ginet
    Philosophical Review 85 (2): 216-224. 1976.
  •  51
    The Significance of Free Will
    Philosophical Review 107 (2): 312. 1998.
    If among the spate of books on free will in recent years there are any that a philosopher concerned with that topic should have handy, this is one of them. Its coverage of the free-will issues debated in the philosophical literature of the last twenty years or so is penetrating, instructive, and by far the most thorough I’ve seen. Kane defends his own positions, but he is unusually fair, even generous, in expounding opposing views. And, while the book is not a popular treatment, it is written in…Read more
  •  131
    Working with Fischer and Ravizza’s Account of Moral Responsibility
    The Journal of Ethics 10 (3): 229-253. 2006.
    This paper examines the account of guidance control given in Fischer and Ravizza's book, Responsibility and Control, with the aim of revising it so as to make it a better account of what needs to be added to having alternatives open to yield a specification of the control condition for responsibility that will be acceptable to an adherent of the principle that one is responsible for something only if one could have avoided it
  •  20
    Philosophy of the Person. P. A. Minkus (review)
    Philosophy of Science 29 (3): 320-322. 1962.
  •  12
    Self-Evidence
    Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 54 (2): 9-31. 2009.
    Este estudo desenvolve uma abordagem do que significa para uma proposição ser autoevidente para alguém, baseado na ideia de que certas proposições são tais que plenamente entendê-las significa crer nelas. Argumenta-se que, quando uma proposição p é autoevidente para alguém, tem-se justificação a priori não-inferencial para crer que p e, eis um traço bem-vindo, uma justificação que não envolve exercer qualquer tipo especial de faculdade intuitiva; se, em adição, é verdade que p e não existe nenhu…Read more
  • On Action
    Mind 100 (3): 390-394. 1990.
  • Libertarianism
    In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 587-612. 2003.
  •  9
    The Works of Agency (review)
    Philosophical Review 109 (4): 632-635. 2000.
    This book comprises eleven essays in the philosophy of action, six of which were previously published. The book has a fairly extensive index. The essays are arranged in four groups. The first group contains two essays on the individuation of action. The second contains four essays that argue for the view that what makes an event an action is, not how it is caused, but that it is, or begins with, a volition, “an intrinsically actional” mental event. The third contains three essays that defend the…Read more
  •  12
    Deciding to Believe
    In Matthias Steup (ed.), Knowledge, Truth and Duty, Oxford University Press. pp. 63-76. 2001.
  •  28
    Review of Richard Holton, Willing, Wanting, Waiting (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (11). 2009.
  •  13
  •  23
    Réplica a Comesaña
    Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 55 (2): 24-32. 2010.
    .
  •  26
    An Incoherence in the Tractatus
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (2): 143-151. 1973.
    In rejecting, In 1929-30, The complete independence of the elementary propositions--According to which any combination of truth-Values for any set of elementary propositions is logically possible--Wittgenstein did not reject an essential element of the "tractatus" system but rather one that fails to cohere with the central picture-Theory of propositions, According to which a method of truth-Valued representation must be capable of presenting 'competing alternative' representations, The false one…Read more
  •  75
    Infinitism is not the solution to the regress problem
    In Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. pp. 140--149. 2013.